The way we respond to color is similar to the way we respond to music: words fail us.
Our perception and understanding of color slips from the realms of rational language,
the sensations stimulate a different part of our brain, triggering emotions that may
not be intellectually grasped, but are still tangibly moving.
Robert Swain’s paintings are the result of an intense 40-year study of color
perception. Standing in front of one of his 10-foot canvases, arranged in a
mathematically formulated grid to minimize perceptual variables and making color
interaction their main concern, there is no denying color has transcendent properties (Figure 1.).
While the actual effects of color may elude description, there is a history of color
theory that can help us speak of this experience. Much like the standardized notes of
the diatonic scale, there are incremental measurements and nuances of color that
reveal the system from which sensation arises.
Color sensation is a more primal response than the narrative we construct around
perception; it is free from cultural and personal encoding, though we may bring these
ideologies into our final “read” of a painting. In this way, Swain’s paintings have the
ability to strip away the constructs we create when taking in the world, instead
directing our attention to the phenomenon of the world itself.
This essay overviews the theoretical issues of Swain’s work to give us the tools to
understand color as an independent subject. There are key objective and identifiable
truths about color that help us understand how color functions. First, it is important
to establish the objective scientific and subjective interpretive at the base of color
perception. With that in place, we can turn our attention to the color system itself,
which will give us the background of objective color measurement, as well as the
observable color phenomena (or the interaction of color) of Swain’s work. Finally,
there is an exploration of Swain’s latest artistic endeavors, both in relation to these
terms and in comparison to his previous work.
In talking about Swain’s paintings, there is a dual impulse. On the one hand, there is a
perceptual response based on scientific fact. On the other, there is the subjective
internalization of that perception. While a color in the world can exist, our observance
of it and transmission from our eyes to our brain is central to our understanding of it.
The works of Sir Isaac Newton and Johann Wolfgang von Goethe in their competing
studies of perception and color best describes this duality.
Central to any discussion of color is the notion that color is actually light. Sir Isaac
Newton was the first to discover this in 1666 and to publish his findings in 1704,
refracting white light through a prism in order to divide it into the separate colored
wavelengths that make up what we call a spectrum. Newton found each particle
moved at different speeds, red moving the fastest and violet the slowest. He then
created the first color wheel based on his observation that the color sequence, as in
the rainbow, is fixed and that violet blends into red. He represented the spectrum as
a full circle, with red green and indigo blue at equal steps.
We have since learned there were certain flaws in Newton’s classifications. Newton
divided his wheel into seven primary colors: red, orange, yellow, green, blue, indigo
and violet. In a spectrum, there are only five discernable separations of color in the
spectrum. Newton’s addition of orange and indigo came from a desire to correspond
the colors of the spectrum to more mystic sources. By corresponding color to the
seven notes of the diatonic scale, Newton was relating an overall “harmony”. By
dividing the color spectrum into seven colors, Newton was tying color to the diatonic
scale in the tradition of Greek sophists, who believed there was a connection between
the colors, the musical notes, and astrology as related to the calendar. Because the
musical scale so easily and irrefutably divides into the magic number seven, so too
should color. In his model of the color wheel, Newton shows how the colors correlate
with musical notes and symbols of the planet. Newton thought anything as
fundamental as color must correspond to the other fundamentals which sophists
grouped into sevens: 7 sacraments, 7 deadly sins, 7 heavenly spheres, 7 days of the
week etc (Burton, p.41).
Nevertheless, without Newton, the science of light and color would not have been
established. Apart from laying the grounds of color theory, Newton brought out the
notion of color functioning as a light. At the root of Swain’s paintings is a belief in
light. Swain juxtaposes certain hues with the expressed purpose of highlighting their
light-emitting qualities. This creates a glow, as each square of the grid interacts with
an adjacent square of different color, producing a myriad of effects as your eye
moves across color relations (Figure 2.).
While Newton was important in establishing the science of color, Goethe brought attention to it from a more romantic and artistic perspective. He argued polemically against Newton’s concept of wavelengths and that there was no color in the physical world, only light and dark. The light patterns are discerned by our eyes and transmitted to our mind, where they are given color. This redirection of emphasis highlights the subjective perceptual (Birren p.105).
It is what gives subject matter to color, making our experience of it meaningful in itself rather than a transmission of different wavelength frequencies. As Swain himself has said, “art is not about establishing scientific truths. It’s about establishing content for people” (Swain, March 18). Swain’s art may rely on scientific phenomena to guide the effects of color interaction, but at the end of the day it is the content of color that is his interest. This moves his work from a textbook description of perception to the actual experience.
With the groundwork of the scientific objective and subjective interpretive established
as a double force in looking at Swain’s work, there must be a way of measuring and
delineating the colors themselves before gauging the effect of their interactions. For
this, a color system must be in place to clearly show the gradation of color.
There have been many different color systems created, but two are of extreme
importance when looking at how Swain derived his own: Albert H. Munsell and Wilhelm
Ostwald.
Ostwald’s color wheel consists of 24 equidistant steps with eight principle hues
(yellow, orange, red, purple, ultramarine blue, turquoise blue, sea green, and leaf
green) each with three steps. The color solid has a gray scale as the central axis,
with colors increasing in purity toward the equator and thirteen steps of gray
between the gradients of black and white. Organized three-dimensionally, each hue
variant is located in a double cone shape, the hues are distributed horizontally and
the white at the top and black at the bottom (Stromer, p.129). It is important to note
that Ostwald forced his colors to fit into the geometric model, working his color
sensations from the outside toward the gray column.
In comparison, Albert Munsell’s system, (Atlas of the Munsell Color System, 1915) moves outward from the gray scale with perceptually equal steps and therefore takes the shape of a distorted sphere. Munsell’s system describes the three dimensions of color by hue (the actual color), value (the lightness or darkness) and saturation (the color’s intensity, or chroma, written as H V/C in the Munsell notation) (Stromer, p.125). Again, it is easiest to grasp the variants when looking at the model three-dimensionally, in order to see the corresponding value changes between colors. Because Munsell did not feel compelled to “fit” his model into a geometric shape, he could account for a larger array of variation. The result is an asymmetrical color tree, closer to a color cloud, with different hues having different variations in value and saturation. It is interesting to note that it was only in the 20th century with Munsell’s system that we have a good color model. It is also interesting to note that a painter and not a scientist created this model! (The updated version of Munsell’s atlas, the Munsell Book of Color, by his son Alexander, is still in use).
For Swain, Ostwald’s system is influential because the relations are based on
harmonies, meaning the interrelatedness of the hues is apparent (Swain, March 18th).
The problem, Swain discovered, was a lack of dark hues. Instead of building
harmonies, Munsell’s system excels at exploiting all the lights and darks of a given
hue, in large part because Munsell refused to constrict his studies to a predetermined
geometry.
In the 1970’s, Swain began developing his color system. Swain’s color system divides
color into 30 hues, 33 value steps, and up to 9 degrees of saturation (Swain, p.188).
Compare this to Munsell’s system, in which each attribute of color has 100 hue steps
(H), based on the five major colors and five intermediaries, each with ten steps; ten
value steps (V) and an open-ended chroma scale © that could reach 12, 14 or more,
depending in the stength of the color, resulting in a total of around 1,250
components. Swain’s color system amounts to 2,200. The colors he derived from his
model do not exist solely in the theoretical paradigm, but from careful measurement
and mixing by hand. This idea of the artist’s touch was also present when Swain
created his color wheel. By staring at a particular hue and then establishing the after
image as the complementary pairing on his wheel, Swain systematically went through
each hue, to create a consistent spatial relation between colors in his devised system
(Figure 3.).
Seeing the three-dimensionality of color is important when looking at Swain’s work. Because of the relationships he establishes between colors within a single work, the individual colors become autonomous agents, interaction and changing depending on contextual relations. The control of hue, value, and saturation in the work explores the specific relationships between specific colors, and, depending on these variables, they will respond differently to each other. This leads us to the topic of color sensation.
There are three major classes of the interaction of color: simultaneous contrast,
successive contrast, and reverse contrast (Ratliff, p.8). These in turn are determined
by three major factors of color perception: composition, viewing distance and
duration, and light source. Each is present in Swain’s work and will be described in
turn.
At the root of color sensation is the concept of simultaneous contrast, termed by
Michel Chevreul in 1839. Simultaneous contrast is the law by which “two adjacent
colors, when seen by the eye, will appear as dissimilar as possible” (Stromer, p.73). In
other words, the perception of a color is affected by the color that surrounds it. This
change is perceptual: a red hue does not literally lighten itself when placed in front of
a violet background as opposed to a yellow, but our mind will “read” it as lighter.
In successive contrast, the perceptual change occurs when observing one color and
then replacing it with another. The optical mixing has to do with after-image, as we
take the information or sensation of the previous color into our reading of the next
one. For example, the same gray will appear greenish when adjacent to red but
reddish when adjacent to green.
The final is reverse contrast, or assimilation, color placed side by side may spread to
adjacent regions, causing colors placed together to appear visually closer or more
alike and a color takes on the hue of the surrounding color. An example would be a
small white square placed on a larger red background and one placed on a larger blue
background. The white square on the red background tends to look reddish, and that
on the blue background becomes bluish. Again, the use of this technique lies in
exploiting the perception of color, as each color is distinct in actuality but will
combine in our brain to create uniformity.
Swain’s Red and Green Circle Untitled, 1969 (Figure 4.) is a perfect example of
Chevreul’s principles. The complementary hues, of equal saturation and value placed
side by side, heighten the unique qualities of both, creating an almost jarring
contrast. However, when looked at for a long duration, a strange effect occurs. First,
a white light appears where they meet. Slowly, the colors optically mix, producing a
neutral grey glowing around the complementary tones—not on the canvas, but in our
mind’s eye.
Three major contextual forces determine the three interactions of color: composition
(referring to the size, shape, number and sharpness of contour of the components of
a painting), viewing distance and duration, and light source.
In essence, Swain only has control over one of the components: composition.
Variables in viewing distance, duration and light source depend on the viewer and the
placement of the painting; someone viewing one of his compositions in sunlight for an
extended period of time will read what he sees differently than someone seeing the
work in fluorescents while quickly walking by.
“Balance is produced by the visual impact of the composition’s components of shape and color” (Arnheim, p. 350).
Swain has established several fixed components in his study of color effect. For
example, his composition by and large is based on a divided grid. For Swain, the use
of the grid helps break color away from iconography (Swain, March 18th). The grid is
basically passive, a vessel in which to carry color information. The sizes of the
squares shift in Swain’s work, depending on the size of the canvas and the desired
color effect. Also, the number of squares change, depending on the actual size of the
painting and compositional balance. Often, Swain will break the grids into larger and
smaller sections, juxtaposing more color contrasts next to a more block-like formation.
All of these decisions are premeditated, and meant to direct the viewer’s experience.
From his 2,200 units of color, Swain derives surprising combinations. For example,
recontextualizing neutrals to elevate their presence on the canvas. “Even the colors
that are very mundane seem to have a personality to me. They have a presence of
substance. The problem is to find a context to exemplify the uniqueness of this, not
in detriment to other colors but in and of themselves” (Swain, March 18th).
There is another experiential effect of Swain’s work that relates to color experience
as laid out by David Katz. Katz classified three ways of seeing color: surface color,
film color, and volume color (Evertz, p. 88), in surface color, the color is seen as
innately tied to the surface of the painting. Film color is the effect of color floating off
the canvas dematerialized, the same way we see endless sky or the hovering glow of
an after-image. Finally, volume color fills a 3-dimensional area of space. Thus, in
contrast to film color, you are able to see within the color itself.
Swain’s paintings traverse all three categories of color experience. Positioning
different patterns of grid, certain areas will remain squarely planted in surface, while
depending on your viewing duration, others will seemingly lift off the canvas. Still
other gradations will seem to project outward, taking on the 3-dimensionality of
volume color (Figure 5)
Swain’s latest work has introduced a critical new variable to the study of color painting: brushstroke. While still working within the confines of a predetermined grid pattern, he has added a textural, free form element to the application of paint. Primarily, Swain has directed his efforts to the interaction to two colors in each painting or grid section. Within a single work, he may vary the size of the brushstroke, but neither color dominates. Instead, they work simultaneously to highlight their inherently unique qualities without loosing any of their own. For example, in Figure 6., as soon as the blue catches your eye, it is equally transfixed on the red. The brushstroke seems to disintegrate toward the lower left quadrant of the canvas, but on closer inspection, the ratio and shape of pattern is proportionate and each brushstroke remains its own unique entity. Instead of modulation through color, the modulation within the painting is through brushstroke size.
These latest series of paintings bring to mind the studies of Georges Seurat, who posited a harmony through synthesis of color (Protter, p.165). The tactility of brushstroke, for Swain, is another way of activating perception (Swain, March 18th). Through his Seurat-like synthesis of color, Swain maintains a dynamic equilibrium, allowing the new paintings to take on the same qualities as his older, but with a new perceptual twist, drawing greater attention to the relational quality of paint. The textural brushstroke emphasizes the surface color in a way his earlier paintings did not, but, because of the color juxtaposition, he still manages to create film and volume color. In this way, his latest work furthers his original studies while activating our eye to acknowledge another dimension of color—tactile movement of the actual paint.
The usefulness of applying language to color perception lies in bringing the
unconscious emotive qualities into an understandable realm. We may never be able to
understand why we feel when we look at color relations, but we can understand how
the color works. There is still the unknowable, which lies in the Goethe-like notion of
subjective response. Robert Swain’s paintings elevate our understanding of
perception, by activating and isolating ways of seeing that are usually taken for
granted. This heightened awareness can only be felt but not grasped. As Swain
himself has said, “this is something you haven’t experienced before. I cannot tell you
how” (Swain, March 18th).
Rachel Stokoe
June 27, 2009
Works Cited
1.Arnheim, Rudolf. “The Expression and Composition of Color.” The Journal of
Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 56, No. 4, (Autumn, 1998), pp.349-352. Blackwell
Publishing.
2.Birren, Faber. “Color Perception in Art: Beyond the Eye into the Brain.” Leonardo,
Vol. 9, No. 2, (Spring, 1976), pp105-110. MIT Press.
3.Burton, David. “Red, Yellow and Blue: The Historical Origin of Color Systems.” Art
Education, Vol. 45, No. 6, (Nov., 1992), pp. 39-44. National Art Education
Association.
4.Evertz, Gabriele. Light Sensations in Painting and Nature. Seeing Red: On
Nonobjective Painting and Color Theory, pp. 84-96. Ed. Michael Fehr and Sanford
Wurmfeld. Salon Verlag, Cologne 2004.
5.Protter, Eric. Painters on Painting, pp. 165-166. New York: Dunlap/Universal Library,
1997
6.Ratliff, Floyd. The Theory of Color and Practice of Painting. Color Function Painting:
The Art of Josef Albers, Julian Stanczak and Richard Anuszkiewics, pp. 5-15. Wake
Forest University Fine Arts Gallery, Winston-Salem, North Carolina, 1996.
7.Rossiter, Jill. The MLA Handbook: Rules for Format & Documentation. U.S.A.: D.W.
Publishing Co. 2008.
8.Swain, Robert. Statement. Seeing Red: On Nonobjective Painting and Color Theory,
pp. 188-190. Ed. Michael Fehr and Sanford Wurmfeld. Salon Verlag, Cologne 2004.
9.Swain, Robert. Personal Interview. 18, March 2009.
10.Stromer, Klaus, Urs Baumann. Color Systems. Trans. Randy Cassada. Konstanz:
Regenbogen Verland Klaus Stromer. Germany, 1996.